Logic and
Language
Load the menuLoad the menu


Copyright   James R Meyer    2012 - 2024 https://www.jamesrmeyer.com

J. R. Lucas on Feferman on Gödel and Free Will

This is a copy of a webpage by J.R. Lucas, undated. It has previously been available in the public domain as published by J. R. Lucas on his webpages before his demise. See the sitemap for other online articles by Lucas.

 

Abstract

Feferman surveys the work of Gödel and Turing, and, although not himself holding a mechanist view of the mind as a whole, raises objections to the anti-mechanist argument put forward by Gödel, Penrose and me, chiefly to our assumption that any mechanism plausibly representing a human mind must be consistent. These objections are countered. In his final section Feferman puts forward his Formalist-Mechanist Thesis II that insofar as human mathematical thought is concerned, mind is mechanical in that it is completely governed by some open-ended schematic formal system. But it is questionable whether an open-ended schematic formal system can be accounted mechanist.

 

o0o

 

Feferman is right to dismiss logical determinism perfunctorily, although it puzzled Aristotle and the medieval Schoolmen and many people still. The inference from “There is going to be either a sea battle tomorrow or not” to “Either there is going to be a sea battle tomorrow or there is not going to be a sea battle tomorrow” is invalid for the same reason as the inference from “I know he is either in his room or in the library” to “Either I know he in his room or I know he is in the library”; ‘is going to be’ is a modal operator, like ‘I know that’, and as in modal logic generally,

 

(p ∨ q) (p ∨ q),

 

on pain of collapse into modal vacuity. Like Ryle, I spent time working through the argument in detail and delving into tense logic, an interesting topic that need not detain us here. (Footnote: J.R.Lucas, The Future, Oxford, 1989.)

 

Feferman gives a careful account of the much-criticized Gödelian argument against mechanism put forward by Gödel, Penrose and me. Like many other critics he highlights our assumption that any plausible mechanical model of the mind must be consistent. Is that assumption justified? By what right do we make out that our understanding of mathematics is consistent? Frege thought his was, and was wrong. How can we be confident that Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZF) does not contain a hidden contradiction that may one day emerge?

 

So far as our understanding of mathematics is concerned, the answer is simple: if ZF turned out to be inconsistent, we should reformulate Set Theory, modifying or abandoning some axiom required for proving the contradiction. There is no guarantee that our current formalisations of mathematics are correct, or consistent. But that is not the point. What is in issue is not the consistency of our current formalisations of mathematics, but the consistency of a purported representation the whole of a person’s mental activity, and hence that his mathematical output is a subset of the set of provable sentences of some formal system. The mechanist might argue for this on empirical grounds - the success of neuro-physiology and, until recently, an over-arching Laplacian determinism. If the empiricist argument succeeded, then the whole of a person’s mental activity could be represented by a mechanism, and hence the whole of his mathematical work. But the Gödelian argument shows that that cannot be the case, and so not only Feferman’s Formalist-Mechanist Thesis I is shown to be false, but the general mechanist thesis too.

 

Feferman complains that we work with highly idealized views of the nature of mind and of mechanism, and that the empirical support for the mechanist thesis cannot be expected to supply a complete perfect description of the workings of the brain any more than of the digestive system. But the mechanist’s “empirical defense” claims that there is such a system, even though it cannot offer a complete perfect description of it. And this system, although not completely or perfectly described by the empirical scientist, must be completely and perfectly describable in principle. If this idealized representation of a particular human mind is consistent, then according to the claim it should not be able to do something that he can do. And if the idealized representation is not consistent, then it is not selective, and does not distinguish between truth and falsity, which a human mind at least sometimes can do. So either way the Formalist-Mechanist Thesis I fails.

 

Many critics fail to distinguish this informal argument from a formal proof of consistency within the idealized representation. “Merely to find from a given machine M a statement S from which it can be proved that M, if consistent, cannot prove S is not to prove S - even if M is consistent.” (Footnote: George Boolos, Introductory note to *1951, Kurt Gödel, Collected Works III, Oxford, 1995, p.295; reprinted in George Boolos, Logic, Logic, and Logic, Cambridge, Mass., 1998, p.110.) But the word ‘prove’ is being used equivocally, the first two times meaning formally proved by M, the third meaning established as true by cogent argument not necessarily confined to the formal proof-procedures of M. The contention that if M were inconsistent, it would not be selective, and hence not a realistic model of a human mind is a cogent argument, though not a formal proof within M, and thus enables a human mind to prove beyond reasonable doubt, though not by a formal proof-sequence generated by M, that if M is made out to be a realistic model of his mind, there is a truth which he can establish and it cannot.

 

But perhaps, it might be suggested, the inconsistency is buried very deep, and only emerges after a long time, if at all. A Nietzschean might maintain that philosophers who persist in thinking too long and too hard about tricky concepts, such as the Self and God, would end up by going mad. It is an intelligible hypothesis. I leave it to others to develop and demolish it.

 

In his last section, Mechanism and partial freedom of the will, Feferman puts forward a mediating position between hard-line mechanism and the anti-mechanist position taken by Gödel, Penrose and me. It depends on an “open-ended schematic axiomatic system”, which is open-ended “in the sense that its basic vocabulary may be expanded to any wider conceptual context in which its notions and axioms may be appropriately applied”. This fits with mathematical practice - witness how the concept of number has been widened from the natural numbers to the integers, the rationals, the reals and the complex numbers - but is difficult to construe within the framework of formal logic. Standardly in logic the range of possible substitution instances is laid down in the initial formulation. The thus circumscribed possibilities are too restricted for many purposes. Feferman’s opening up the range of admissible substitution extends these possibilities in an interesting way, and may yield valuable insights into the nature of mathematical thinking - which does, indeed, progress as much by the recognition of concepts as by the discovery of derivations. But even if its axiom schemata and rules of inference are fixed, a system with open-ended rules of substitution is not going to give the hard-line mechanist what he wants, and would be compatible with an open-ended and creative view of the human mind. The hard-line mechanist is offering an explanation of the “Why Necessarily?” type, in contrast to others, including some connectionists, who merely seek to explain How Possibly the brain could work. (Footnote: I owe this crucial distinction to W.H.Dray. See his “Explanatory Narrative in History”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 1954, pp.15-27; or his Laws and Explanation in History, Oxford, 1957, ch.6.) The latter may be called mechanists, but their conclusions, though illuminating, do not have determinist consequences, any more than evolutionists who explain how reptiles evolved into birds are committed to holding that the evolutionary path actually taken was one that had to go in that pre-determined way.

Footnotes:

Interested in supporting this site?

You can help by sharing the site with others. You can also donate at Go Get Funding: Logic and Language where there are full details.

 

 

As site owner I reserve the right to keep my comments sections as I deem appropriate. I do not use that right to unfairly censor valid criticism. My reasons for deleting or editing comments do not include deleting a comment because it disagrees with what is on my website. Reasons for exclusion include:
Frivolous, irrelevant comments.
Comments devoid of logical basis.
Derogatory comments.
Long-winded comments.
Comments with excessive number of different points.
Questions about matters that do not relate to the page they post on. Such posts are not comments.
Comments with a substantial amount of mathematical terms not properly formatted will not be published unless a file (such as doc, tex, pdf) is simultaneously emailed to me, and where the mathematical terms are correctly formatted.


Reasons for deleting comments of certain users:
Bulk posting of comments in a short space of time, often on several different pages, and which are not simply part of an ongoing discussion. Multiple anonymous user names for one person.
Users, who, when shown their point is wrong, immediately claim that they just wrote it incorrectly and rewrite it again - still erroneously, or else attack something else on my site - erroneously. After the first few instances, further posts are deleted.
Users who make persistent erroneous attacks in a scatter-gun attempt to try to find some error in what I write on this site. After the first few instances, further posts are deleted.


Difficulties in understanding the site content are usually best addressed by contacting me by e-mail.

 

Based on HashOver Comment System by Jacob Barkdull

Copyright   James R Meyer   2012 - 2024
https://www.jamesrmeyer.com