Footnotes:
Hilbert’s tenth problem
Page last updated 25 Jun 2024
in 1900 the mathematician David Hilbert posed twenty-three problems that were at that time all unanswered. His tenth problem was the question as to whether, given any Diophantine equation,
A Diophantine equation is a polynomial equation with integer coefficients and a finite number of unknown variables, for example,
In 1970 Yuri Matiyasevich claimed to have completed a proof that proved Hilbert’s question in the negative, that is there can be no finite method which can deduce, for any given Diophantine equation, whether there is a solution of the equation where all the variables take only integer values. Matiyasevich’s work utilized previous results by others, and for this reason it is commonly referred to as the MRDP theorem, named after Yuri Matiyasevich, Julia Robinson, Martin Davis and Hilary Putnam.
Torkel Franzen. Gödel’s Theorem: An Incomplete Guide to its Use and Abuse. A K Peters, 2005. ISBN: 1568812388, and
an online article PDF The MRDP Theorem by the convicted paedophile ex-professor Peter Smith claiming that the MRDP “theorem” can be used to prove incompleteness.)
There is an English translation of the full text of Matiyasevich’s proof in the book Hilbert’s Tenth Problem. (Footnote:
Yuri Matiyasevich, Hilbert’s Tenth Problem , MIT press, 1993, ISBN 0-262-13295-8.)
In the following we will analyze the proof presented in that book.
Naming of variables
Conventionally, while it is common to see names such as
Furthermore, if numerical subscripts are desired, there is no logical reason that requires the subscripts of the variables and parameters to be in the same numerical format as the format of the numbers that form the domain of natural numbers for the variables/
Variable names in the MRDP proof
In the Section 3.2 Gödel coding, Matiyasevich states:
Consider an arbitrary tuple:
Let
be any pairwise co-prime numbers such that:
By the Chinese Remainder Theorem, we can find a number
Thus all the elements of tuple (3.2.1) are uniquely determined by the numbers:
He continues:
… we have great freedom in choosing the numbers (3.2.2), and we can choose them to be determined by just a few numbers. For example, put
A little further on he says:
… we call the triple
where
In 3.2.1 to 3.2.6 the terms
Since it is the case that there is no inherent naming method for the variables, then if one intends to use a single symbol (such as
However, consider Matiyasevich’s claim that:
We can assert that by consideration of the right side of the equation, both
On the other hand, what about the term
One can, however, say of the left side that
where
But a function and its variables can have any name, for example we could call it
It follows that the term
Self-reference
That erroneous equivalence is used to make the mathematical system appear to self-reference, to be able to refer to such matters as the length of formulas of the system and to positions of its coefficients, etc, by its very own formulas, which makes it appear that the system can somehow infer certain information about its own formulas, even though its own axioms and rules of inference are completely agnostic regarding such information. (Footnote:
For example, the equations
As already pointed out, if one wants to use numerical subscripts, then a simple way to reduce the possibility of any confusion of levels of language is to use different formats for the subscripts. Matiyasevich uses standard base 10 positional notation for natural numbers that constitute the domain of his variables for natural numbers. This means that there is no logical reason why, for example, a format such as
I have demonstrated in many places elsewhere on this site how a confusion of different levels of language are often the basis of fallacious arguments. Many of these arguments claim to demonstrate that a well-formed logical mathematical system can self-reference itself.
Torkel Franzen and others claim that the MRDP proof leads to a proof of incompleteness without invoking any self-reference, and consider that this aspect of the MRDP “theorem” has tremendous significance. Franzen says: (Footnote: From Torkel Franzen. Gödel’s Theorem: An Incomplete Guide to its Use and Abuse. A K Peters, 2005)
As for the contrasting of the “new viewpoint” with “the old proof based on the paradox of the liar,” … the MRDP theorem shows that every theory to which the incompleteness theorem applies leaves undecided infinitely many statements of the form “the Diophantine equation
But, as shown above, a logical analysis demonstrates that self-reference is in fact involved in the MRDP proof and hence such claims are fallacious.
Conclusions
At this point I want to make it quite clear that I am not anywhere asserting that it is impossible that there can be a proof that a formal system having certain properties is incomplete. A claim of a proof of incompleteness that relies on a confusion of levels of language is not a proof, it is only the semblance of a proof, where at some point the proof relies on some form of self-reference (whether explicit or hidden) and which is the result of an illogical confusion of levels of language. This sort of confusion of levels of language cannot occur within a properly formulated logically valid formal language.
It is a mystery why mathematicians and logicians appear unwilling to contemplate the possibility that a confusion of levels of language can result in arguments that have no logical validity, and seem to never consider that they should examine proofs carefully to ascertain whether this might be the case. Of course, once you start pretending that there isn’t an elephant in the room, not only do you not set out to look for it, you actively avoid doing so, instead concentrating your attention anywhere but in that direction.
Rationale: Every logical argument must be defined in some language, and every language has limitations. Attempting to construct a logical argument while ignoring how the limitations of language might affect that argument is a bizarre approach. The correct acknowledgment of the interactions of logic and language explains almost all of the paradoxes, and resolves almost all of the contradictions, conundrums, and contentious issues in modern philosophy and mathematics.
Site Mission
Please see the menu for numerous articles of interest. Please leave a comment or send an email if you are interested in the material on this site.
Interested in supporting this site?
You can help by sharing the site with others. You can also donate at where there are full details.