Logic and
Language
Load the menuLoad the menu


Copyright   James R Meyer    2012 - 2024 https://www.jamesrmeyer.com

A Step by Step Guide to Gödel’s Incompleteness Proof:
3: Axioms and rules of the formal system


 

 


 

Page last updated 28 Dec 2022

 

Now printer friendly: this guide has now been set up for easy printing so that readers can also access the information in paper format.

 

Note that (provided you have JavaScript enabled) clicking on () will reveal further details, while clicking again will hide it. Also, clicking on () will reveal relevant parts of Gödel’s text (shown in green), while clicking again will hide it.

 

(like this)

 

(like this)

If there is any difficulty in following any part of the proof, please contact me and I will try to help. And if you have any suggestions as to how this guide might be improved, please contact me. This guide is intended to be read alongside the English translation of Gödel’s original proof which can be viewed online at English translation of Gödel’s original proof.

 

The axioms and rules of the formal system

As is the case for the formal system P in general, the precise details of the axioms of this system are not important. It might be wondered whether the system P has sufficient axioms and rules of inference - that perhaps some detail has been omitted which renders the system not powerful enough to be complete. But this would be to miss the point - which is that Gödel’s proof can in principle be applied to any formal system (provided it contains a certain amount of basic arithmetic, such as defining natural numbers and basic operations on those numbers). So that even if there was some deficiency in the system P, the overall thrust of the argument would remain and be applicable to all formal systems which include a basic arithmetical core. That said, you still need to be familiar with the terminology that Gödel uses if you are to follow the principle of Gödel’s argument.

 

Note that, while in most logical systems in common use today, every variable in an axiom is bound by a quantifier, in Gödel’s system P, this is not the case - the axioms can have variables which are not bound by a quantifier. However, every such axiom can be converted to a formula in which all the variables are bound, as will be seen below.

 

The rules of inference of the system P

There are two rules of inference ().

  1. If the formula (¬(b)) (c) is an axiom or is a proven formula, and b is an axiom or is proved, then the formula c is proved.
  2. If the formula a is an axiom or is a proven formula, then the formula v(a) is proved, where v is any variable.

“A formula c is called an immediate consequence of a and b, if a is the formula (¬(b)) (c), and an immediate consequence of a, if c is the formula v(a), where v denotes any given variable. The class of provable formulae is defined as the smallest class of formulae which contains the axioms and is closed with respect to the relation ‘immediate consequence of ’. ”

 

Hence, given an axiom or proven formula whose variables are not bound by a quantifier, by repeated application of rule 2 we can obtain the same formula where each variable is bound by a quantifier.

 

The axioms of the system P

Gödel divides the axioms into five sections. Note that the axioms II, III, and V are actually Axiom Schemas; this means that each ‘axiom’ actually represents infinitely many axioms; in such Schemas, there are meta-language variables, and an axiom of the formal system is obtained when specific values are substituted for these meta-language variables. For example, for the Axiom Schema II.1 below (p p ⊃ p), we could replace p by any formula of the formal system to give a single axiom.

 

Note: the axioms as given include some symbols which are not actually symbols of the formal system P. The reason for this is as follows:

The system P uses a very small set of symbols. There are several symbols in common usage which are effectively abbreviations for long combinations of the basic symbols of the system P. Gödel uses these symbols because the actual representation in the notation of the system P would be very lengthy and difficult to read. The symbols Gödel uses are listed is below, along with the equivalent representation by symbols of the formal system P:

 

 

Note that Gödel, in the original German, also uses the symbol “.” in the axiom I.3; this is equivalent to the symbol.

 

Note that, for convenience Gödel follows convention in omitting some brackets that would be present in the actual corresponding formula of the formal system. For example, in the following, wherever the symbol (the ‘implies’ symbol) occurs, all of the expression to the left of the symbol implies all of the expression to the right of the symbol, unless that part of the expression containing the symbol is enclosed by brackets.

 

Axioms I:

These are elementary axioms about natural numbers.

 

1.  ¬(fx1 = 0)

No successor of a number can be equal to zero.

 

2.  fx1 = fy1 ⊃  x1 = y1

Given two numbers, if we add one to each number, and the resultant numbers are equal, then that implies (the symbol) that the original numbers are both equal.

 

3.  x2(0) ∧ x1(x2(x1) ⊃ x2(fx1))  ⊃  x1(x2(x1))

This is what is usually called an axiom of induction. Given any class of natural numbers, if 0 is a member of that class, and if, for every natural number x1, if x1 being a member of that class implies that x1 + 1 is also a member of that class, then every natural number is a member of that class.

 

Axioms II:

These are Axiom Schemas, based on axioms of classical propositional logic. In the Schemas below p, q and r can be any formula of the formal system.

 

1.  p p  ⊃  p

For any formula p, p or p implies p.

 

2.  p  ⊃  p q

For any formula p, p implies ‘p or any other formula q’.

 

3.  p q  ⊃  q p

For any formulas p and q, ‘or q’ implies ‘q or p’.

 

4.  (p ⊃ q)  ⊃  (r p  ⊃  r q)

For any formulas p, q and r, ‘p implies q’ implies that ‘(r or p) implies (r or q)’

 

Axioms III:

In these Axiom Schemas,

a is any formula,

v is any variable,

b is a formula and

c is a string;

b and c are subject to certain conditions ().

 

“Every formula derived from the two schemata by making the following substitutions for a, v, b, c (and carrying out in I the operation denoted by “Subst”): for a any given formula, for v any variable, for b any formula in which v does not appear free, for c a string of the same type as v, provided that c contains no variable which is bound in a at a place where v is free.
c is therefore either a variable or 0 or a string of the form f…fu where u is either 0 or a variable of type 1.”

 

1.  v(a)  ⊃  Subst a(v|c)

This states that, if for all v, formula a applies, then every formula given by the substitution of a valid value c for v applies.

 

As Gödel notes, the Subst function is a function of the meta-language, not of the formal system P. So while there is no expression of the formal system that corresponds to the above expression when values are simply inserted for a, b, c, and v, there are formulas that correspond to the expressions given when appropriate values are inserted for a, b, c, and v and the value given by the meta-language function Subst a(v|c) (which is a symbol string of the system P) is substituted in place of Subst a(v|c).

 

Note that normally we use the term substitution to refer to the substitution of a variable by a specific value which is a member of the domain of the variable. Here Subst allows variables to be substituted by variables, provided they are of the same type, subject to certain conditions; this is akin to changing the names of the variables in a formula.

 

2.  v(b a)  ⊃  b v(a)

This states that, ‘if for all v, b or a’ applies, then ‘b or for all v, a’ applies (provided that there are not any free variables in b).

 

Axiom IV:

In this Axiom Schema,

v and u are variables, where u is one type higher than v, and

a is formula which does not have u as free variable

 

1.  (∃u)(v(u(v) ≡ a))

For every formula, there is a corresponding class whose members satisfy that formula.

 

Axiom V:

In this axiom we have type 1 and type 2 variables.

 

1.  x1(x2(x1) ≡ y2(x1))  ⊃  x2 = y2

If two classes have precisely the same members, then they are identical.

 

Further axioms are defined by this axiom by applying Type-lift to the basic formula above.

Footnotes:

 


 

 


 

Interested in supporting this site?

You can help by sharing the site with others. You can also donate at Go Get Funding: Logic and Language where there are full details.

 

 

As site owner I reserve the right to keep my comments sections as I deem appropriate. I do not use that right to unfairly censor valid criticism. My reasons for deleting or editing comments do not include deleting a comment because it disagrees with what is on my website. Reasons for exclusion include:
Frivolous, irrelevant comments.
Comments devoid of logical basis.
Derogatory comments.
Long-winded comments.
Comments with excessive number of different points.
Questions about matters that do not relate to the page they post on. Such posts are not comments.
Comments with a substantial amount of mathematical terms not properly formatted will not be published unless a file (such as doc, tex, pdf) is simultaneously emailed to me, and where the mathematical terms are correctly formatted.


Reasons for deleting comments of certain users:
Bulk posting of comments in a short space of time, often on several different pages, and which are not simply part of an ongoing discussion. Multiple anonymous user names for one person.
Users, who, when shown their point is wrong, immediately claim that they just wrote it incorrectly and rewrite it again - still erroneously, or else attack something else on my site - erroneously. After the first few instances, further posts are deleted.
Users who make persistent erroneous attacks in a scatter-gun attempt to try to find some error in what I write on this site. After the first few instances, further posts are deleted.


Difficulties in understanding the site content are usually best addressed by contacting me by e-mail.

 

Based on HashOver Comment System by Jacob Barkdull

Copyright   James R Meyer   2012 - 2024
https://www.jamesrmeyer.com