This page is keyboard accessible:
• Use Tab, Shift + Tab keys to traverse the main menu. To enter a sub-menu use the Right Arrow key. To leave a sub-menu use the Left Arrow or the Escape key.
• The Enter or the Space key opens the active menu item.
• To skip the menu and move to the main content, press Tab after the page loads to reveal a skip button.
• To get back to the top of the page anytime, press the Home key.
• For more information, click here: Accessibility   Close this tip.

Note: Full functionality of this web page requires JavaScript to be enabled in your browser.
 

The Courant & Robbins Contradiction

In the book, What is Mathematics? by Courant and Robbins, (Footnote: Courant & Robbins, What is mathematics? pub: Oxford University Press, New York, 2nd ed. 1996, Ch 4, section 2, pp 82-83. ISBN­10: 0195105192. (First edition, 1941) What is Mathematics?: details.) there is a proof that there are more real numbers than natural numbers, a proof that, intriguingly, is not based on one of Cantor’s well-known proofs. It appears that it was Courant and Robbins who originally came up with the proof, although it can be seen mentioned elsewhere. (Footnote: Sondheimer & Rogerson, Numbers and Infinity, pub: Cambridge University Press, 1st ed, 1981, ISBN­10: 0521284333, Ch 11, pp 152-153 Numbers and Infinity: details.
Gregory Chaitin has made several references to the proof, see:
   a) Chaitin, Algorithmic Information Theory, pub: Cambridge University Press, 2004, ISBN­13: 978­0521616041 (Section 7.1), this part of the book is based on Chaitin’s 1987 paper ‘Incompleteness theorems for random reals’.
   b) Chaitin, Thinking About Gödel And Turing, Essays On Complexity, 1970-2007, pub: World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd. ISBN­13 978­9812708953 (Section 2.2: Alternate proof: Any countable/denumerable set of reals has measure zero.)
   c) Chaitin, Meta Math, The Quest for Omega, pub: Pantheon, First Edition, 2005, ISBN­13: 978­0375423130 (Chapter Five, Section: ‘Reals are uncomputable with probability one’)
John Stillwell, in the book Roads to Infinity: The Mathematics of Truth and Proof (CRC Press, 2010 Roads to Infinity: details) claims that Carl Gustav Axel von Harnack was the first to come up with this proof in 1885; however he provides no reference to where one might find Harnack’s proof.)

 

It is easy to demonstrate that the argument is inherently flawed. However, the interesting thing about it is that a logical analysis of the underlying argument shows that the Platonist belief in the independent ‘actual’ existence of limitlessly many mathematical entitles is inherently illogical, because it shows that that belief leads to a contradiction. The demonstration of the contradiction in the proof by Courant and Robbins serves to demonstrate the untenability of the Platonist viewpoint.

 

The Courant and Robbins proof goes like this:

  1. Suppose that there can be a list (for definition of what is meant by a list, see one-to-one correspondence) that includes all of the real numbers. For our purposes, we will only consider the real numbers between 0 and 1. For convenience we will use the concept of the real number line between 0 and 1, and which represents all the real numbers between 0 and 1. The ‘proof’ operates by enclosing every real number in the list between 0 and 1 by a small length of a line as follows:
    1. For the first real number in the supposed list of all real numbers, we make a line segment that is 110 wide, and which includes that real number (note that the number can be anywhere within this line segment).
    2. For the second real number in the list, make a line segment 1100 wide, enclosing that real number.
    3. For the third real number in the list, make a line segment 11000 wide, enclosing that real number.
    4. And so on, through the list, for all the real numbers. As long as the appropriate real number is within the correct line segment, it is immaterial precisely where in that line segment it lies.
  2. The proof says that if every real number between 0 and 1 is actually in the list, then the entire line between 0 and 1 must be covered by this infinite series of line segments whose lengths get progressively smaller: 110, 1100, 11000, 110000, 1100000
  3. Of course, some of the line smaller segments may overlap. But, says the proof, even if there were no overlapping at all, the actual total length of all our line segments is the sum of all the lengths
    110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 1100000
  4. The proof says that the sum of all these lengths is 19, because 110 + 1100 + 11000 + … is what is called a standard geometric series, and the proof says that it is a standard result that the sum of such a series as 19 (See Appendix: Geometric Series).
  5. The proof continues: Since, even if there is overlapping, the sum of the segments cannot be greater than 19, and that since that is less than the total length of the line segment from 0 to 1 (which is a length of 1), then we cannot actually have included all the real numbers in the line segments that we used.
  6. Therefore, the ‘proof’ continues, the original supposition that could be a complete listing of the real numbers must have been incorrect, and there cannot be a listing of all the real numbers. Because of that, there must be more real numbers than natural numbers.

 

It’s almost embarrassingly easy to show that this argument results in a contradiction, which shows that it cannot possibly be correct. It is well known that the rational numbers (numbers that are fractions) between 0 and 1 can be listed (See Appendix: Listing the rational numbers). They can be set in a list so that for any natural number, there is a corresponding fraction between 0 and 1, and every rational number between 0 and 1 is included in this list. Since that is the case, we can apply the same argument as in the proof above to the fractions between 0 and 1.

 

And by the argument of the proof, the conclusion is, similarly, that since the list includes every fraction between 0 and 1, then we know that every fraction must be enclosed by one of these line segments 110, 1100, 11000 … etc, regardless of how small that segment may be. And, again, according to the argument of the proof, the sum of these line segments cannot be more than 19, whereas the entire line segment between 0 and 1 is a length of 1. That means that there must be some remaining part of the line that isn’t made up of any combination of any of the line segments 110, 1100, 11000 … .

 

But – the problem is that if we have any line segment on the real number line, there has to be a real number at each end of the line segment, and between any two real numbers, there must always be at least one fraction in that line segment - in fact, there will be limitlessly many fractions in that line segment.

 

We now have a contradiction, which I will call the Courant & Robbins contradiction’. (Footnote: Here we do not euphemistically call it a paradox, and by so doing, imply that there just appears to be a contradiction – there is a genuine contradiction here which cannot be brushed aside.) The argument says that the line segments 110, 1100, 11000, … cover every fraction; but they cannot cover the entire distance between 0 and 1, so that there must be at least one other line segment, that is not one of the line segments 110, 1100, 11000, … that contains at least one fraction. And this is always the case regardless of the choice of size of the line segments, as long as the initial fraction is less than 12 (for example, we could choose 13 or 157 instead of 110).

 

When we have a contradiction, that means that the argument is flawed, and that at least one step in the argument must be rejected as incorrect. So what is going on? Where is the flawed step in the argument?

 

The Platonist view is that all real numbers are some sort of ‘actual’ things that ‘exist’ in some sense in some ‘reality’, and that they exist simultaneously in this ‘reality’ - and any section of the real number line consists of a limitlessness quantity of points, and that all those points simultaneously ‘exist’ in some sense as ‘actual’ things. The Platonist also believes that every line segment of real numbers ‘exists’ in this ‘reality’, and all of these line segments ‘exist’ simultaneously. So, accordingly, from the Platonist viewpoint, in the Courant & Robbins contradiction, all the line segments 110, 1100, 11000 … ‘exist’, and all ‘exist’ simultaneously. And the sum of all of these line segments also ‘exists’ and is 19.

 

But if you are not a Platonist there is no contradiction, and the notion of a ‘sum’ of a limitless quantity of line segments simply doesn’t arise. To see the reason why there is no contradiction for the non-Platonist, consider the Courant & Robbins argument:

 

110110

 

110 + 110011100

 

110 + 1100 + 110001111000

 

110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000111110000

 

110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 110000011111100000

 

We see the pattern quite easily, which is

 

110, 11100, 1111000, 1111110000, 11111100000, 1111111000000

 

And similarly, when we try to divide 1 by 9 on a calculator, we get 0.1111111111111111. On your calculator, depending on the display panel or how it operates, you might get a different quantity of 1’s. And if you did the calculation by hand, you can add more and more 1’s the longer you calculate for. Theoretically, there is no limit to the quantity of 1’s you could calculate; but one thing is for sure – you will never calculate more than a finite quantity of 1’s.

 

If we look at the pattern that is

 

110, 11100, 1111000, 1111110000, 11111100000, 1111111000000

 

it leads us to suspect that these values are all approaching a value of 19. This can be confirmed by a formula given by commonly accepted mathematical logic (See Appendix: Geometric Series) but we would be careful to note 19 is a limiting value that the values never actually reach. The formula is not the value of the sum of a limitless sum of fractions.

 

It might be worth pointing out here that, generally speaking, mathematicians aren’t very rigorous when they talk about things that involve limitlessness. Often we see ‘numbers’ written as a sequence of decimal digits with three dots at the end, like this, 0.21382349… The three dots at the end are subject to various interpretations. (Footnote: When it is said, for example, that 0.1326472… is a number, where the … signifies continuing into infinity, in fact this not signify any particular number. What it does actually signify is a set of real number values that lie between the values 0.1326472 and 0.1326473.) Often mathematicians will talk about the ‘sum’ of an infinite series of fractions, when what they actually are referring to is not to an actual sum of an infinite quantity of fractions, but to a limit – a limit that cannot be exceeded by the sum of any finite series of fractions. In most cases, the distinction doesn’t matter, but sometimes it does.

 

When it comes to the notion (as in the Courant & Robbins proof) that we form a one-to-one correspondence of every line segment to a fraction, what this notion actually involves is a definition which simply defines limitlessly many single correspondences, and there is no limit to the quantity of such correspondences. This definition does not require the ‘existence’ of limitless quantities of fractions or of line segments; it is simply a valid logical definition, and it has no dependence on any Platonist beliefs. So when the Courant & Robbins contradiction states that the sum of a limitless quantity of fractions of the form 110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 1100000 + … is 19, the response of a non-Platonist is that that is incorrect. He has no need of any notion such as the sum of a limitless quantity of fractions. For the non-Platonist, there isn’t any contradiction at all in the increasingly smaller line segments scenario. He doesn’t need to believe that these line segments actually exist in some ‘reality’, and he doesn’t need to believe that a sum of all a limitless quantity of line segments ‘exists’. All he does is to observe that the only statements that he can make about these line segments are logical statements regarding the definitions involved, some of which involve limitlessness. And he observes that the process of continually making further line segments never actually finishes, and so a point is never reached where there is a contradiction. For the non-Platonist, the limit of the sums of such fractions as 110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 1100000 + … is 19, but he also acknowledges that that limit is never actually reached. (Footnote: Historically, there have been intense arguments about whether a limitlessness could be considered as completed.)

 

But while the Courant & Robbins contradiction isn’t a contradiction for the non-Platonist, and doesn’t present any difficulties for the non-Platonist, for the Platonist it is an entirely different matter. He cannot state that the sum of a limitless quantity of mathematical entities does not ‘exist’ – because it is a cornerstone of Platonist philosophy that sums of limitless quantities of mathematical entities do ‘exist’, and moreover, that they ‘exist’ independently of any human definition. (Footnote: For example Platonists believe that there are real numbers that are the sum of a limitless number of fractions and which can never be defined by any finite means – and that means that they can only ‘exist’ as ‘actual’ Platonist things.)

 

So, from the point of view of the Platonist:

  • a limitless quantity of line segments such as 110, 1100, 11000, 110000 … actually ‘exists’, and
  • the sum of such a limitless quantity of line segments ‘exists’ and the value of that sum is 19, and
  • the pairing of every rational number (between 0 and 1) and some line segment such as 110, 1100, 11000, 110000 … ‘exists’,

and the combination of these beliefs results in a contradiction.

 

A line segment is simply a part of a line that defines a set of all numbers greater than (or greater than or equal to) a given value and less than (or less than or equal to) a given value, so, since the Platonist insists that the sum of an infinite quantity of fractions does ‘exist’, he cannot logically argue that such line segments don’t ‘exist’. Similarly, it would be absurd for a Platonist to argue that while the sum of an infinite quantity of fractions does ‘exist’, the sum of an infinite quantity of line segments cannot ‘exist’.

 

The Courant & Robbins contradiction is a compelling argument against Platonism in mathematics. It demonstrates that the Platonist belief that the sum of a limitless quantity of fractions such as 110 + 1100 + 11000 + … ‘exists’, and is the same ‘actual’ thing as the value we refer to as ‘19’, is logically untenable.

 

For the non-Platonist, every one of these fractions 110, 1100, 11000, 110000 … is a finite size, however small it may be; and all the fractions are interrelated, since every fraction is 110 of a previous fraction. And every fraction is related to the first fraction, which is 110 by being multiplied by 110 a finite number of times, that is, every such fraction can be expressed as (110)n where n is some natural number. That means that all such fractions, by the very definition of the series, are of finite size; there cannot be any one of these fractions that is not a definite determined size. But the Platonist view that all such fractions ‘exist’ requires that there ‘exists’ more than a finite quantity of such fractions – and that requires that there must be fractions that are related to the first fraction (which is 110) by being multiplied by 110 a limitless number of times. But the Platonist cannot give any value for 110 multiplied by itself a limitless number of times. He cannot give it any finite value, and neither can he give it a value of zero – because, according to the Platonist creed, there ‘exist’ in some reality, limitlessly many such fractions which consist of 110 multiplied by itself a limitless number of times, so they can’t all be the value of zero. Of course, the non-Platonist can say that the limiting value as you repeatedly multiply 110 by 110 over and over again is zero, that is, the value of (110)n approaches zero as the value of n gets bigger and bigger – but it never reaches that value. But that is of no help to the Platonist when faced with the Courant & Robbins contradiction. He has no way of circumventing the absurdity of the Platonist viewpoint that the sum of more than a finite quantity of such fractions ‘exists’.

 

And more …

For more demonstrations of contradictions arising from the Platonist beliefs in the ‘existence’ of ‘actual’ infinite sets, see Sums of infinitely many fractions: 1 and Sums of infinitely many fractions: 2,

 

 

Footnotes:

 

 

Appendix: Geometric Series

For a limitlessly long geometric series in the form of

Series of fractions

the sum of the first n + 1 terms is:

Fraction Expression

Provided the value of r is greater than 1, then the value of  Fraction Expression  decreases as n increases, and the limiting value of  Fraction Expression  as n increases is zero.

 

That gives the standard result that the limiting value of the sum as n increases, provided r is greater than 1 is:

Fraction Expression  which is the same as  Fraction Expression

 

For the series 110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 1100000r is 10, and so the limit of the sum as n increases is given as

Fraction Expression

which evaluates as 19. And that means that, no matter how many terms are in the series, the value of the series can never exceed the value 19. To put it another way, the limiting value that any such sum of a finite quantity of terms approaches, but never actually reaches, is 19. Note that the quantity

Fraction Expression

in the formula can never actually be zero; every fraction that is in the series is of the form

Fraction Expression

where y is always some finite number. There is no fraction in the series where y is not some finite number.

Note that 0.999… is usually used to indicate the limiting value of the series:

910 + 9100 + 91000 + 910000 + 9100000

Since this is the same as 9 × (110 + 1100 + 11000 + 110000 + 1100000 …), then the limiting value is 9 × 19, which is 1.

 

Appendix: Listing the rational numbers

There is more than one way of making a list of the rational numbers. An easy way is demonstrate is to visualize a method, by using horizontal rows, the first with all fractions with 1 on the top, the next row with all the fractions with 2 on the top, and so on, like this:

List of rationals 1

Then we can envisage a simple way of progressing through the fractions so as to not miss any on the way. We can do this by taking each column in turn, like this:

List of rationals 2

This scheme outlines a way of listing all the positive rational numbers. Although it is a visual scheme, there is no reason why the methodology could not be defined without using any visual cues. Of course, the list never finishes, and that is because there is no limit to the quantity of rational numbers. You might notice that in this scheme some numbers are repeated, since 11 = 22, and 21 = 42. This is true, but the important point is that the scheme doesn’t omit any rational numbers. And if you wanted to include negative numbers, then you do the same scheme except that you simply include a negative of each number immediately after each number.

If you want to list only the fractions between say, 0 and 1, then you simply leave out the fractions that are greater than one, like this:

List of rationals 3

and make a list in the same way as before.

 

 

Diverse opinions and criticisms are welcome, but messages that are frivolous, irrelevant or devoid of logical basis will be blocked (comments will be checked before appearing on this site). Difficulties in understanding the site content are usually best addressed by contacting me by e-mail. Note: you will be asked to provide an e-mail address - this will only be used to notify you of replies to your comments - it will never be used for any other purpose, will never be displayed and does not require verification. Comments are common to the entire website, so please indicate what section of the site you are commenting on.

 

If you cannot see any comments below, it may be that a plug-in on your browser is blocking Disqus comments from loading. Avast anti-virus in particular is known to do this, especially with Internet Explorer and Safari. See Disqus Browser plug-in/extension conflicts or Why isn’t the comment box loading?.

 

 

Please wait for comments to load …  

 

The Lighter Side

 

NEWS

There’s something about Gödel by Francesco Berto

There is a new addition to the page Yet another flawed incompleteness proof, where Berto’s proof of incompleteness in his book There’s something about Gödel comes under scrutiny.

 

 

Easy Footnotes

I found that making, adding or deleting footnotes in the traditional manner proved to be a major pain. So I developed a different system for footnotes which makes inserting or changing footnotes a doddle. You can check it out at Easy Footnotes for Web Pages (Accessibility friendly).

 

 

O’Connor’s “computer checked” proof

I have now added a new section to my paper on Russell O’Connor’s claim of a computer verified incompleteness proof. This shows that the flaw in the proof arises from a reliance on definitions that include unacceptable assumptions - assumptions that are not actually checked by the computer code. See also the new page Representability.

 

 

New page on Chaitin’s Constant

There is now a new page on Chaitin’s Constant (Chaitin’s Omega), which demonstrates that Chaitin has failed to prove that it is actually algorithmically irreducible.

 

 

Updated: Diagonal Lemma

Flawed proofs of the Diagonal Lemma by Panu Raatikainen and Vann McGee have been added to the Diagonal Lemma web page.

Previous Blog Posts  

 

16th Mar 2015 Bishops Dancing with Pixies?

 

23rd Feb 2015 Artificial Intelligence

 

31 Mar 2015 Cranks and Crackpots

 

30 Apr 2015 The Chinese Room

 

Links  

 

For convenience, there are now two pages on this site with links to various material relating to Gödel and the Incompleteness Theorem

 

– a page with general links:

Gödel Links

 

– and a page relating specifically to the Gödel mind-machine debate:

Gödel, Minds, and Machines

 

Printer Friendly

 

All pages on this website are printer friendly, and will print the main content in a convenient format. Note that the margins are set by your browser print settings.


Note: for some browsers JavaScript must be enabled for this to operate correctly.

 

Comments

 

Comments on this site are welcome, please see the comment section.

 

Please note that this web site, like any other is a collection of various statements. Not all of this web site is intended to be factual. Some of it is personal opinion or interpretation.

 

If you prefer to ask me directly about the material on this site, please send me an e-mail with your query, and I will attempt to reply promptly.

 

Feedback about site design would also be appreciated so that I can improve the site.

 


Copyright © James R Meyer 2012 - 2016  
www.jamesrmeyer.com